The
Works of Aristotle: Rhetoric (Rhetorica)
Quotes
for Discussion
Accordingly, all men make use, more or less, of both; for to a certain
extent all men attempt to discuss statements and to maintain them, to defend
themselves, and to attack others. Ordinary people do this either at random or
through practice and from acquired habit.
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book I, chapter 1, Great Books Volume 9, pg 593
This is sound law and custom. It is not right to pervert the judge by
moving him to anger or envy or pity – one might as well warp a carpenter’s rule
before using it.
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book I, chapter 1, Great Books Volume 9, pg 593
Rhetoric is useful (1) because things that are true and things that are
just have a natural tendency to prevail over their opposites, so that if the
decisions of judges are not what they out to be, the defeat must be due to the
speakers themselves, and they must be blamed accordingly. Moreover (2) before
some audiences not even the possession of the exactest knowledge will make it
easy for what we say to produce conviction. For argument based on knowledge
implies instruction, and there are people whom one cannot instruct. Here, then,
we must use modes of persuasion and argument, notions possessed by everybody,
as we observed in the Topics when dealing with the way to handle a popular
audience.
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book I, chapter 1, Great Books Volume 9, pg 594
And if it be objected that one who uses such power of speech unjustly
might do great harm, that is a charge which may be made in common against all good
things except virtue, and above all against the things that are most useful, as
strength, health, wealth, generalship. A man can confer the greatest of
benefits by a right use of these, and inflict the greatest of injuries by using
them wrongly.
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book I, chapter 1, Great Books Volume 9, pg 594
A probability is a thing that usually happens not, however as some
definitions would suggest, anything whatever that usually happens but only if
it belongs to the class of the contingent or variable. It bears the same
relation to that in respect of which it is probable as the universal bears to
the particular.
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book I, chapter 2, Great Books Volume 9, pg 597
It may be said that every individual man and all men in common aim at a
certain end which determines what they choose and what they avoid. This end, to
sum it up briefly, is happiness and its constituents.
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book I, chapter 5, Great Books Volume 9, pg.600
Good also are the things by which we shall gratify our friends or annoy
our enemies; and the things chosen by those whom we admire; and the things for
which we are fitted by nature or experience, since we think we shall succeed
more easily in these: and those in which no worthless man can succeed, for such
thins bring greater praise; and those which we do in fact desire, for what we
desire is taken to be not only pleasant but also better.
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book I, chapter 6, Great Books Volume 9, pg.604
Noble also are those actions whose advantage may be enjoyed after death,
as opposed to those whose advantage is enjoyed during one’s lifetime; for the
latter are more likely to be for one’s own sake only. Also, all actions done
for the sake of others, since less than other actions are done for one’s own
sake; and all successes which benefit others and not oneself, and services done
to one’s benefactors, for this is just; and good deed generally, since they are
not directed to one’s own profit.
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book I, chapter 9, Great Books Volume 9, pg.609
So are the distinctive qualities of a particular people, and the symbols
of what it specially admires, like long hair in Sparta, where this is a mark of
a free man, as it is not easy to perform any menial task when one’s hair is
long. Again it is noble not to practice any sordid craft, since it is the mark
of a free man not to live at another’s beck and call.
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book I, chapter 9, Great Books Volume 9, pg.610
… good fathers are likely to have good sons, and good training is likely
to produce good character. Hence it is only when a man has already done
something that we bestow encomiums upon him. Yet the actual deeds are evidence
of the doer’s character; even if a man has not actually done a given good
things, we shall bestow praise on him, if we are sure that he is the sort of
man who would do it.
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book I, chapter 9, Great Books Volume 9, pg.610
You may feel that even if you are found out you can stave off a trial, or
have it postponed, or corrupt your judges; or that even if you are sentences
you can avoid paying damages, or can at least postpone doing so for a long
time; or that you are so badly off that you will have nothing to lose. You may
feel that the gain to be got by wrong-doing is great or certain or immediate,
and that the penalty is small or uncertain or distant. It may be that the
advantage to be gained is greater than any possible retribution; as in the case
of despotic power, according to the popular view.
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book I, chapter 12, Great Books Volume 9, pg.616
In order to be wrongs, a man must (1) suffer actual harm, (2) suffer it
against his will. The various possible forms of harm are clearly explained by
our previous separate discussion of goods and evils
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book I, chapter 13, Great Books Volume 9, pg.618
Now it often happens that the man will admit an act, but will not admit
the prosecutor’s label for the act nor the facts which that label implies. He
will admit that he took a thing but not that he “stole” it;
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book I, chapter 13, Great Books Volume 9, pg.618
There are three kinds of slighting – contempt, spite, and insolence (1)
contempt is one kind of slighting; you feel contempt for what you consider
unimportant, and it is just such things that you slight, (2) Spite is another
kind; it is thwarting another man’s wishes, not to get something yourself but
to prevent his getting it. The slight arises just from the fact that you do not
aim at something for yourself; clearly you do not think that he can do you
harm, for then you would be afraid of him instead of slighting him, not yet
that he can do you any good worth mentioning, for then you would be anxious to
make friends with him. (3) Insolence is also a form of slighting, since it
consists in doing and saying things that cause shame to the victim, not in
order that anything may happen to yourself, or because anything has happened to
yourself, but simply for the pleasure involved (Retaliationin not insolence,
but vengeance.)
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book 2, chapter 2, Great Books Volume 9, pg.623
Here we have a Maxim; add the reason or explanation, and the whole thing
is an Enthymem; thus
It makes them idle; and therewith they earn Ill-will and jealously
throughout the city.
Again,
There is no man in all things prosperous,
And
There is no man among us all is free,
Are maxims; but the latter, taken with what follows it, is an Enthymeme –
For all are slaves of money or of chance.
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book 2, chapter 21, Great Books Volume 9, pg.642
…if a man happens to have had neighbours or bad children, he will agree
with any one who tells hi, “Nothing is more annoying than having neighbours” or
“nothing is more foolish than to be the parent of children.” The e orator has
therefore to guess the subjects on which his hearers really hold views already,
and what those views are, and then must express as general truths, these same
views on these same subjects. This is one advantage of using maxims. There is
another which is more important – in invests a speech with moral character. There
is a moral character in every speech in which the moral purpose is conspicuous;
and maxims always produce this effect, because the utterance of them amounts to
a general declaration of moral principles; so that if the maxim are sound, they
display the speaker as a man of sound moral character, So much for the Maxim –
its nature, varieties, proper use, and advantages.
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book 2, chapter 21, Great Books Volume 9, pg.643
The special facts here needed are those that are true of Achilles along;
such facts as that he slew Hector, the bravest of the Trojans, and Cycnus the
invulnerable, who prevented all the Greeks from landing, and again that he was
the youngest man who joined the expedition, and was not bound by oath to join
it, and so on.
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book 2, chapter 22, Great Books Volume 9, pg.644
Another is the argument from consequence. In the Alexander, for instance,
it is argued that Paris must have had a lofty disposition, since he despised
society and lived by himself on Mount Ida: because lofty people do this kind of
thing, therefore Paris too, we are to suppose, had a lofty soul. Of, if a man
dresses fashionable and roams around at night he is a rake, since that is the
way rakes behave.
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book 2, chapter 24, Great Books Volume 9, pg.650
In making a speech one must study three points; first, the means of
producing persuasion; second, the style, or language, to be used; third, the
proper arrangement of the various parts of the speech.
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book 3, chapter 1, Great Books Volume 9, pg.653
Our next subject will be the style of expression. For it is not enough to
know what we ought to say; we must also say it as we ought; much help is thus
afforded towards producing the right impression of speech.
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book 3, chapter 1, Great Books Volume 9, pg.653
The right thing in speaking really is that we should be satisfied not to
annoy our hearers, without trying to delight them; we ought in fairness to
fight our case with no help beyond the bare facts; nothing, therefore, should
matter except the proof of those facts. Still, as has been already said, other
things affect the result considerably, owing to the defects of our hearers.
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book 3, chapter 1, Great Books Volume 9, pg.654
The arts of language cannot help having a small but real importance,
whatever it is we have to expound to others; the way in which a thing is said
does affect its intelligibility. Not, however, so much importance as people
think. All such arts are fanciful and meant to charm the hearer. Nobody uses
fine language when teaching geometry.
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book 3, chapter 1, Great Books Volume 9, pg.654
(Take as an example the introduction to the Helen of Isocrates - there is
nothing in common between the 'eristics' and Helen.) And here, even if you
travel far from your subject, it is fitting rather than that there should be
sameness in the entire speech.
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book 3, chapter 14, Great Books Volume 9, pg.668
The appeal to the hearer aims at securing his goodwill or at arousing his
resentment, or sometimes at gaining his serious attention to the case or even
at distracting it - for gaining it is not always an advantage and speakers will
often for that reason try to make him laugh.
You may use any means you choose to make your hearer receptive; among others giving him a good impression of your character which always helps to secure his attention. He will be ready to attend to anything that touches himself and to anything that is important surprising or agreeable; and you should accordingly convey to him the impression that what you have to say is of this nature. If you wish to distract his attention you should imply that the subject does not affect him or is trivial or disagreeable. But observe, all this has nothing to do with the speech itself. It merely has to do with the weak-minded tendency of the hearer to listen to what is beside the point. When this tendency is absent no introduction is wanted beyond a summary statement of your subject to put a sort of head on the main body of your speech.
You may use any means you choose to make your hearer receptive; among others giving him a good impression of your character which always helps to secure his attention. He will be ready to attend to anything that touches himself and to anything that is important surprising or agreeable; and you should accordingly convey to him the impression that what you have to say is of this nature. If you wish to distract his attention you should imply that the subject does not affect him or is trivial or disagreeable. But observe, all this has nothing to do with the speech itself. It merely has to do with the weak-minded tendency of the hearer to listen to what is beside the point. When this tendency is absent no introduction is wanted beyond a summary statement of your subject to put a sort of head on the main body of your speech.
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Book 3, chapter 14, Great Books Volume 9, pg.669
Vocabulary – Rhetoric
The Works of Aristotle, Rhetoric
(Rhetorica), Great Books Volume 9
divarication, pg 648, a difference of opinion, a divergence of opinion
enthymeme, pg 596
An enthymeme (Greek:ἐνθύμημα, enthumēma), in its modern sense, is an
informally stated syllogism (a three-part deductive argument) with an
unstatedassumption that must be true for the premises to lead to the
conclusion.
An informally stated syllogism with an implied premise.
syllogism, pg 596
a form of argument that contains a major premise, a minor premise and a
conclusion.
A form of deductive reasoning consisting of a major premise, a minor
premise, and a conclusion.
The Major Premise of a syllogism contains the predicate of the conclusion
and the middle term.